English philosopher and physician (1632–1704)
For other people named John Locke, see John Locke (disambiguation).
John LockeFRSPortrait of John Locke,by Godfrey Kneller (1697)BornJohn Locke(1632-08-29)29 August 1632Wrington, Somerset, EnglandDied28 October 1704(1704-10-28) (aged 72)High Laver, Essex, EnglandEducationChrist Church, Oxford (BA, 1656; MA, 1658; MB, 1675)EraAge of EnlightenmentRegionWestern philosophySchool
Empiricism
Foundationalism[1]
Conceptualism[2]
Indirect realism[3]
Correspondence theory of truth[4]
Ideational theory of meaning[5]
Corpuscularianism[6]
Social contract
Natural law
Liberalism
Classical liberalism
Academic careerInfluencesCicero[7]DescartesEpicurus[8]
InstitutionsUniversity of Oxford[9]Royal SocietyMain interestsMetaphysics, epistemology, political philosophy, philosophy of mind, philosophy of education, economicsNotable ideas
List
Consciousness
Consent of the governed
Inverted spectrum
Labor theory of property
Law of opinion
Lockean proviso
Molyneux's problem
Argument from ignorance[10][11]
Natural rights (rights of life, liberty and property)[12]
Primary/secondary quality distinction
Semeiotike (the doctrine of signs)
Social contract
Sortal
State of nature
Tabula rasa
Signature
Part of a series onJohn Locke
Social contract
Limited government
Tabula rasa
State of nature
Right to property
Labor theory of property
Lockean proviso
Argument from consciousness
Works(listed chronologically)
Fundamental Constitutionsof Carolina
A Letter Concerning Toleration
Two Treatises of Government
An Essay ConcerningHuman Understanding
Some ThoughtsConcerning Education
Of the Conduct ofthe Understanding
People
Robert Filmer
Thomas Hobbes
1st Earl of Shaftesbury
David Hume
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
Adam Smith
Immanuel Kant
Thomas Jefferson
Related topics
Empiricism
Classical liberalism
Polish Brethren
vte
John Locke's portrait by Godfrey Kneller, National Portrait Gallery, London
John Locke (/lɒk/; 29 August 1632 (O.S.) – 28 October 1704 (O.S.))[13] was an English philosopher and physician, widely regarded as one of the most influential of the Enlightenment thinkers and commonly known as the "father of liberalism".[14][15][16] Considered one of the first of the British empiricists, following the tradition of Francis Bacon, Locke is equally important to social contract theory. His work greatly affected the development of epistemology and political philosophy. His writings influenced Voltaire and Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and many Scottish Enlightenment thinkers, as well as the American Revolutionaries. His contributions to classical republicanism and liberal theory are reflected in the United States Declaration of Independence.[17] Internationally, Locke's political-legal principles continue to have a profound influence on the theory and practice of limited representative government and the protection of basic rights and freedoms under the rule of law.[18]
Locke's philosophy of mind is often cited as the origin of modern conceptions of personal identity and the psychology of self, figuring prominently in the work of later philosophers, such as Rousseau, David Hume, and Immanuel Kant. He postulated that, at birth, the mind was a blank slate, or tabula rasa. Contrary to Cartesian philosophy based on pre-existing concepts, he maintained that we are born without innate ideas, and that knowledge is instead determined only by experience derived from sense perception, a concept now known as empiricism.[19] Locke is often credited for describing private property as a natural right, arguing that when a person—metaphorically—mixes their labour with nature, resources can be removed from the common state of nature.[20][21]
Early life[edit]
Locke was born on 29 August 1632, in a small thatched cottage by the church in Wrington, Somerset, about 12 miles (19 km) from Bristol. He was baptised the same day, as both of his parents were Puritans. Locke's father, also named John, was an attorney who served as clerk to the Justices of the Peace in Chew Magna,[22] and as a captain of cavalry for the Parliamentarian forces during the early part of the English Civil War. His mother was Agnes Keene. Soon after Locke's birth, the family moved to the market town of Pensford, about seven miles south of Bristol, where Locke grew up in a rural Tudor house in Belluton.
In 1647, Locke was sent to the prestigious Westminster School in London under the sponsorship of Alexander Popham, a member of Parliament and John Sr.'s former commander. At the age of 16 he was at school just half a mile away from the execution of Charles I; however, the boys were not allowed to go and watch. After completing studies at Westminster, he was admitted to Christ Church, Oxford, in the autumn of 1652 at the age of 20. The dean of the college at the time was John Owen, vice-chancellor of the university. Although a capable student, Locke was irritated by the undergraduate curriculum of the time. He found the works of modern philosophers, such as René Descartes, more interesting than the classical material taught at the university. Through his friend Richard Lower, whom he knew from the Westminster School, Locke was introduced to medicine and the experimental philosophy being pursued at other universities and in the Royal Society, of which he eventually became a member.[citation needed]
Locke was awarded a bachelor's degree in February 1656 and a master's degree in June 1658.[9] He obtained a bachelor of medicine in February 1675,[23] having studied the subject extensively during his time at Oxford. In addition to Lower, he worked with such noted scientists and thinkers as Robert Boyle, Thomas Willis, and Robert Hooke. In 1666, he met Anthony Ashley Cooper, Lord Ashley, who had come to Oxford seeking treatment for a liver infection. Ashley was impressed with Locke and persuaded him to become part of his retinue. At Oxford, he was exposed to the writings of Islamic scholars, such as Ibn Tufayl's Hayy ibn Yaqdhan translated by Edward Pococke, who influenced his perspectives on philosophy and tabula rasa.[24][25][26][27]
Career[edit]
Work[edit]
Locke had been looking for a career and in 1667, moved into Ashley's home at Exeter House in London, to serve as his personal physician. In London, Locke resumed his medical studies under the tutelage of Thomas Sydenham. Sydenham had a major effect on Locke's natural philosophical thinking—an effect that would become evident in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Locke's medical knowledge was put to the test when Ashley's liver infection became life-threatening. Locke coordinated the advice of several physicians and was probably instrumental in persuading Ashley to undergo surgery (then life-threatening in itself) to remove the cyst. Ashley survived and prospered, crediting Locke with saving his life. During this time, Locke served as Secretary of the Board of Trade and Plantations and Secretary to the Lords Proprietors of Carolina, which helped to shape his ideas on international trade and economics.[28]
Ashley, as a founder of the Whig movement, exerted great influence on Locke's political ideas. Locke became involved in politics when Ashley became Lord Chancellor in 1672 (Ashley being created 1st Earl of Shaftesbury in 1673). Following Shaftesbury's fall from favour in 1675, Locke spent some time travelling across France as a tutor and medical attendant to Caleb Banks.[29] He returned to England in 1679 when Shaftesbury's political fortunes took a brief positive turn. Around this time, most likely at Shaftesbury's prompting, Locke composed the bulk of the Two Treatises of Government. While it was once thought that Locke wrote the Treatises to defend the Glorious Revolution of 1688, recent scholarship has shown that the work was composed well before this date.[30] The work is now viewed as a more general argument against absolute monarchy (particularly as espoused by Robert Filmer and Thomas Hobbes) and for individual consent as the basis of political legitimacy. Although Locke was associated with the influential Whigs, his ideas about natural rights and government are considered quite revolutionary for that period in English history.
The Netherlands[edit]
Locke fled to the Netherlands in 1683 in the company of Shaftesbury, under strong suspicion of involvement in the Rye House Plot, although there is little evidence to suggest that he was directly involved in the scheme. While in the Netherlands, he lived under the pen-name dr. Van Linden.[31] The philosopher and novelist Rebecca Newberger Goldstein argues that during his five years in Holland, Locke chose his friends "from among the same freethinking members of dissenting Protestant groups as Spinoza's small group of loyal confidants [Baruch Spinoza had died in 1677], Locke almost certainly met men in Amsterdam who spoke of the ideas of that renegade Jew who ... insisted on identifying himself through his religion of reason alone." While she says that "Locke's strong empiricist tendencies" would have "disinclined him to read a grandly metaphysical work such as Spinoza's Ethics, in other ways he was deeply receptive to Spinoza's ideas, most particularly to the rationalist's well thought out argument for political and religious tolerance and the necessity of the separation of church and state."[32] Among the friends he made in the Netherlands are Van Leeuwenhoek and Van Limborch, the leader of the Remonstrants.[31] In the Netherlands, Locke had time to return to his writing, spending a great deal of time working on the Essay Concerning Human Understanding and composing the Letter on Toleration.
Return to England[edit]
Locke did not return home until after the Glorious Revolution. Locke accompanied Mary II back to England in 1689. The bulk of Locke's publishing took place upon his return from exile—his aforementioned Essay Concerning Human Understanding, the Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration all appearing in quick succession. Locke's close friend Lady Masham invited him to join her at Otes, the Mashams' country house in Essex. Although his time there was marked by variable health from asthma attacks, he nevertheless became an intellectual hero of the Whigs. During this period, he discussed matters with such figures as John Dryden and Isaac Newton.
Death[edit]
Engraved memorial plaque at Oxford
After a lengthy period of poor health,[33] Locke died on 28 October 1704, and is buried in the churchyard of All Saints' Church in High Laver, near Harlow in Essex, where he had lived in the household of Sir Francis Masham since 1691.[34] Locke never married nor had children. Events that happened during Locke's lifetime include the English Restoration, the Great Plague of London, the Great Fire of London, the Glorious Revolution and war against France including the Battle of Blenheim just before his death. He did not live long enough to see the Act of Union of 1707, but the thrones of England and Scotland were held in personal union throughout his lifetime. Constitutional monarchy and parliamentary democracy were in their infancy during Locke's time. Locke has an engraved floor memorial plaque at Christ Church Cathedral, Oxford.[35]
Philosophy[edit]
Portrait of John Locke by John Greenhill (died 1676)
In the late 17th and early 18th centuries, Locke's Two Treatises were rarely cited. Historian Julian Hoppit said of the book "except among some Whigs, even as a contribution to the intense debate of the 1690s it made little impression and was generally ignored until 1703 (though in Oxford in 1695 it was reported to have made 'a great noise')."[36] John Kenyon, in his study of British political debate from 1689 to 1720, has remarked that Locke's theories were "mentioned so rarely in the early stages of the [Glorious] Revolution, up to 1692, and even less thereafter, unless it was to heap abuse on them" and that "no one, including most Whigs, [was] ready for the idea of a notional or abstract contract of the kind adumbrated by Locke".[37]: 200 In contrast, Kenyon adds that Algernon Sidney's Discourses Concerning Government were "certainly much more influential than Locke's Two Treatises."[i][37]: 51
In the 50 years after Queen Anne's death in 1714, the Two Treatises were reprinted only once (except in the collected works of Locke). However, with the rise of American resistance to British taxation, the Second Treatise of Government gained a new readership; it was frequently cited in the debates in both America and Britain. The first American printing occurred in 1773 in Boston.[38] Locke exercised a profound influence on political philosophy, in particular on modern liberalism. Michael Zuckert has argued that Locke launched liberalism by tempering Hobbesian absolutism and clearly separating the realms of Church and State. He had a strong influence on Voltaire, who called him "le sage Locke". His arguments concerning liberty and the social contract later influenced the written works of Thomas Jefferson. One passage from the Second Treatise is reproduced verbatim in the Declaration of Independence, the reference to a "long train of abuses". Concerning Locke, Jefferson wrote:[39][40][41]
Bacon, Locke and Newton ... I consider them as the three greatest men that have ever lived, without any exception, and as having laid the foundation of those superstructures which have been raised in the Physical and Moral sciences.
Locke's influence may have been even more profound in the realm of epistemology. Locke redefined subjectivity, or the self, leading intellectual historians such as Charles Taylor and Jerrold Seigel to argue that Locke's An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1689/90) marks the beginning of the modern Western conception of the self.[42][43] Locke's theory of association heavily influenced the subject matter of modern psychology. At the time, Locke's recognition of two types of ideas, simple and complex—and, more importantly, their interaction through association—inspired other philosophers, such as David Hume and George Berkeley, to revise and expand this theory and apply it to explain how humans gain knowledge in the physical world.[44] Locke thought the state's borders and the functioning and enforcement of the existence of the state and its constitution were metaphysically tied to "the natural rights of the individual", and this inspired future liberal politicians and philosophers.[45]
Religious tolerance[edit]
See also: Toleration § Locke
John Locke by Richard Westmacott, University College London
Writing his Letters Concerning Toleration (1689–1692) in the aftermath of the European wars of religion, Locke formulated a classic reasoning for religious tolerance, in which three arguments are central:[46]
earthly judges, the state in particular, and human beings generally, cannot dependably evaluate the truth-claims of competing religious standpoints;
even if they could, enforcing a single 'true religion' would not have the desired effect, because belief cannot be compelled by violence;
coercing religious uniformity would lead to more social disorder than allowing diversity.
With regard to his position on religious tolerance, Locke was influenced by Baptist theologians like John Smyth and Thomas Helwys, who had published tracts demanding freedom of conscience in the early 17th century.[47][48][49][50] Baptist theologian Roger Williams founded the colony of Rhode Island in 1636, where he combined a democratic constitution with unlimited religious freedom. His tract, The Bloudy Tenent of Persecution for Cause of Conscience (1644), which was widely read in the mother country, was a passionate plea for absolute religious freedom and the total separation of church and state.[51] Freedom of conscience had had high priority on the theological, philosophical, and political agenda, as Martin Luther refused to recant his beliefs before the Diet of the Holy Roman Empire at Worms in 1521, unless he would be proved false by the Bible.[52]
Slavery and child labour[edit]
Locke's views on slavery were multifaceted. Although he wrote against slavery in general, Locke was an investor and beneficiary of the slave-trading Royal Africa Company. While secretary to the Earl of Shaftesbury, Locke also participated in drafting the Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina, which established a quasi-feudal aristocracy and gave Carolinian planters absolute power over their enslaved chattel property; the constitutions pledged that "every freeman of Carolina shall have absolute power and authority over his negro slaves". Philosopher Martin Cohen observes that Locke, as secretary to the Council of Trade and Plantations and a member of the Board of Trade, was "one of just half a dozen men who created and supervised both the colonies and their iniquitous systems of servitude".[53][54] According to American historian James Farr, Locke never expressed any thoughts about his contradictory opinions of slavery, which Farr ascribes to his personal involvement in the Atlantic slave trade.[55] Locke's positions on slavery have been described as hypocritical, and laying the foundation for the Founding Fathers to hold similarly contradictory thoughts regarding freedom and slavery.[56]
Historian Holly Brewer argues that Locke's role in the Constitution of Carolina has been exaggerated and that he was merely paid to revise and make copies of a document that had already been partially written before he became involved; she compares Locke's role to a lawyer writing a will.[57] She states that Locke was paid in Royal African Company stock in lieu of money for his work as a secretary for a governmental sub-committee, and that he sold the stock after a few years.[58] Brewer likewise argues that Locke actively worked to undermine slavery in Virginia while heading a Board of Trade created by William of Orange following the Glorious Revolution. He specifically attacked colonial policy granting land to slave owners and encouraged the baptism and Christian education of the children of enslaved Africans to undercut a major justification of slavery—that they were heathens who possessed no rights.[59]
In his Two Treatises of Government, Locke provided a justification for slavery that could never be met, thus rendering invalid all forms of slavery that existed. Moreover, because slavery is invalid, there is a moral injunction to try to throw off and escape from it.[citation needed] Locke also supported child labour, which was an intrinsic part of all pre-industrial societies.[60][61] In his "Essay on the Poor Law", he discusses the education of the poor; he laments that "the children of labouring people are an ordinary burden to the parish, and are usually maintained in idleness, so that their labour also is generally lost to the public till they are 12 or 14 years old".[62]: 190 Therefore, he suggests the setting up of "working schools" for poor children in each parish in England so that they will be "from infancy [three years old] inured to work".[62]: 190 He goes on to outline the economics of these schools, arguing not only that they will be profitable for the parish, but also that they will instil a good work ethic in the children.[62]: 191
Government[edit]
See also: Two Treatises of Government
Part of the Politics seriesRepublicanism
Concepts
Anti-monarchism
Anti-corruption
Civic virtue
Civil society
Consent of the governed
Democracy
Democratization
Liberty as non-domination
Mixed government
Political representation
Popular sovereignty
Public participation
Republic
Res publica
Rule of law
Self-governance
Separation of powers
Social contract
Social equality
Schools
Classical
Federal
Kemalism
Khomeinism
Modern
Nasserism
Neo-republicanism
Venizelism
Types
Autonomous
Capitalist
Christian
Democratic
Federal
Imperial
Islamic
Maritime
Parliamentary
Peasant
People's
Revolutionary
Secular
Sister
Soviet
Philosophers
Arendt
Baggini
Bello
Bentham
Bodin
Cattaneo
Chappell
Cicero
Condorcet
Crick
Franklin
Harrington
Honderich
Jefferson
Kant
Locke
Machiavelli
Madison
Mazzini
Mill
Montesquieu
Paine
Pettit
Polybius
Rousseau
Sandel
Sidney
Sunstein
Tocqueville
Warburton
Wollstonecraft
Politicians
Adams (Gerry)
Adams (John)
Atatürk
Azaña
Bartley
Benn
Bennett
Bolívar
Chapman
Clark (Katy)
Clarke (Tom)
Connolly
Cromwell
Davidson
Drakeford
Etherington
Fabiani
Ferguson
Flynn
Gambetta
Garibaldi
de Gaulle
Grévy
Griffith
Griffiths
Harvie
Hatton
Hébert
Hopkins
Huppert
Iorwerth
Jackson
Jay
Jefferson
Jones (Elin)
Jones (Lynne)
Juárez
Kane
Khomeini
La Malfa
Lewis
Lincoln
Lucas
Mackay
Mackenzie
Madison
Magid
Mannin
McDonnell
McKechin
Mullin
Nandy
Naysmith
Nehru
Pound
Prescott
Ritchie
Robespierre
Sayed
Skates
Skinner
Slater
Slaughter
Smith
Spadolini
Sun
Taverne
Venizelos
Wilson
Wood
Theoretical works
Republic (c. 375 BC)
De re publica (54–51 BC)
Discourses on Livy (1531)
The Tenure of Kings and Magistrates (1649)
The Commonwealth of Oceana (1656)
Discourses Concerning Government (1698)
The Spirit of Law (1748)
Discourse on Inequality (1755)
The Social Contract (1762)
The Federalist Papers (1787–1788)
Rights of Man (1791)
Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1794)
Democracy in America (1835–1840)
On Revolution (1963)
History
Roman Republic
Gaṇasaṅgha
Classical Athens
Republic of Venice
Republic of Genoa
Republic of Florence
Dutch Republic
American Revolution
French Revolution
Spanish American wars of independence
Trienio Liberal
French Revolution of 1848
5 October 1910 revolution
Chinese Revolution
Russian Revolution
German Revolution of 1918–1919
Turkish War of Independence
Mongolian Revolution of 1921
11 September 1922 Revolution
1935 Greek coup d'état attempt
Spanish Civil War
1946 Italian institutional referendum
1952 Egyptian revolution
14 July Revolution
North Yemen Civil War
Zanzibar Revolution
1969 Libyan coup d'état
1970 Cambodian coup d'état
Metapolitefsi
Iranian Revolution
1987 Fijian coups d'état
Nepalese Civil War
Barbadian Republic Proclamation
National variants
Antigua and Barbuda
Australia
Bahamas
Barbados
Canada
Ireland
Jamaica
Japan
Morocco
Netherlands
New Zealand
Norway
Spain
Sweden
United Kingdom
Scotland
Wales
United States
Related topics
Classical radicalism
Common good
Communitarianism
Criticism of monarchy
Egalitarianism
The Emperor's New Clothes
Jacobinism
Liberalism
List of republics
Monarchism
Peasant republic
Primus inter pares
Republic without republicans
Republican empire
Republican Party
Politics portalvte
Part of a series onLiberalism
History
Age of Enlightenment
List of liberal theorists (contributions to liberal theory)
Principles
Consent of the governed
Due process
Democracy
Economic liberalism
Economic globalization
Equality
Gender
Legal
Federalism
Freedom
Economic
Market
Trade
Press
Religion
Speech
Harm principle
Internationalism
Invisible hand
Labor theory of property
Laissez-faire
Liberty
Negative
Positive
Limited government
Market economy
Natural monopoly
Open society
Permissive society
Popular sovereignty
Property
Private
Public
Rights
Civil and political
Natural and legal
To own property
To bear arms
Rule of law
Secularism
Secular humanism
Separation of church and state
Separation of powers
Social contract
Social justice
Social services
Welfare state
Whig history
Philosophers
Milton
Locke
Spinoza
Montesquieu
Voltaire
Rousseau
Smith
Kant
Turgot
Burke
Priestley
Paine
Beccaria
Condorcet
Bentham
Korais
De Gouges
Wollstonecraft
Staël
Say
Humboldt
Constant
Ricardo
Guizot
List
Bastiat
Martineau
Emerson
Tocqueville
Mill
Spencer
Arnold
Acton
Weber
Hobhouse
Croce
Cassirer
Mises
Ortega
Keynes
Collingwood
Čapek
Hu
Hayek
Popper
Aron
Berlin
Friedman
Rawls
Sen
Nozick
Kymlicka
Badawi
Politicians
Jefferson
Kołłątaj
Madison
Artigas
Bolívar
Broglie
Lamartine
Macaulay
Kossuth
Deák
Cobden
Mazzini
Juárez
Lincoln
Gladstone
Cavour
Sarmiento
Mommsen
Naoroji
Itagaki
Levski
Kemal
Deakin
Milyukov
Lloyd George
Venizelos
Ståhlberg
Gokhale
Rathenau
Madero
Einaudi
King
Roosevelt
Pearson
Ohlin
Kennedy
Jenkins
Balcerowicz
Verhofstadt
Obama
Macron
Organizations
Africa Liberal Network
Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe
Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe Party
Arab Liberal Federation
Council of Asian Liberals and Democrats
European Democratic Party
European Liberal Youth
International Alliance of Libertarian Parties
International Federation of Liberal Youth
Liberal International
Liberal Network for Latin America
Liberal parties
Liberal South East European Network
Regional variants
Europe
Latin America
Albania
Armenia
Australia
Austria
Belgium
Bolivia
Brazil
Bulgaria
Canada
Chile
China
Hong Kong
Colombia
Costa Rica
Croatia
Cuba
Cyprus
Czechia
Denmark
Ecuador
Egypt
Estonia
Finland
France
Georgia
Germany
Greece
Venizelism
Honduras
Hungary
India
Iran
Israel
Italy
Liberism
Japan
Latvia
Lithuania
Luxembourg
Mexico
Moldova
Montenegro
Netherlands
New Zealand
Nicaragua
Nigeria
North Macedonia
Norway
Panama
Paraguay
Peru
Philippines
Poland
Cracovian
Portugal
Romania
Russia
Senegal
Serbia
Slovakia
Slovenia
South Africa
South Korea
Spain
Sweden
Switzerland
Taiwan
Thailand
Tunisia
Turkey
Ukraine
United Kingdom
Cobdenism
Gladstonian
Manchester
Whiggism
United States
Arizona School
Classical
Jeffersonian
Modern
Uruguay
Venezuela
Zimbabwe
Related topics
Anti-authoritarianism
Anti-communism
Bias in American academia
Bias in the media
Capitalism
Democratic
Centrism
Radical centrism
Economic freedom
Egalitarianism
Empiricism
Humanism
Individualism
Anarchist
Land value tax
Libertarianism
Left
Right
Pirate Party
Progressivism
Sexually liberal feminism
Utilitarianism
Schools
Classical
Conservative
Cultural
Feminist
Equity
Green
Internationalist
Muscular
National
Neoclassical
Neo
Ordo
Radical
Religious
Christian
Catholic
Islamic
Jewish
Secular
Social
Techno
Third Way
Liberalism portal
Politics portalvte
Part of a series onLibertarianism
Concepts
Abstention
Academic freedom
Age of consent reform
Anti-authoritarianism
Anti-capitalism
Antimilitarism
Anti-statism
Artistic freedom
Civil liberties
Class struggle
Cognitive liberty
Counter-economics
Crypto-anarchism
Decentralization
Decriminalization of sex work
Departurism
Drug liberalization
Direct action
Economic freedom
Egalitarianism
Evictionism
Expropriative anarchism
Federalism (anarchist)
Free association (Marxism and anarchism)
Free love
Free market
Free-market environmentalism
Free migration
Free trade
Freedom of assembly
Freedom of association
Freedom of choice
Freedom of conscience
Freedom of contract
Freedom of information
Freedom of religion
Freedom of speech
Freedom of thought
Gift economy
Homestead principle
Illegalism
Individualism
Individualist feminism
Individual reclamation
Liberty
Libertarianism (metaphysics)
Localism
Natural law
Natural rights and legal rights
Night-watchman state
Non-aggression principle
Non-interventionism
Participatory economics
Propaganda of the deed
Property is theft!
Refusal of work
Reproductive rights
Right to die
Right to privacy
Right to sexuality
Self-governance
Self-ownership
Single tax
Social ecology
Spontaneous order
Squatting
Stateless society
Tax resistance
Voluntary association
Voluntary society
Workers' councils
Workers' self-management
Issues
Abortion
Affirmative action
Anarcho-capitalism and minarchism
Capital punishment
Criticism
Foreign intervention
Immigration
Intellectual property
Internal debates
LGBT rights
Objectivism
Political alliances
Political parties
Theories of law
War on Drugs
Philosophers
La Boétie
Locke
Franklin
Burke
Paine
Jefferson
Bentham
Godwin
Hodgskin
Warren
Emerson
Stirner
Spooner
Proudhon
Andrews
Bakunin
Thoreau
Spencer
Herbert
George
De Cleyre
Goldman
Gandhi
Mises
Paterson
Hayek
Rand
Friedman (Milton)
Bookchin
Hess
Rothbard
Chomsky
Nozick
Machan
Block
Friedman (David)
Van Dun
Konkin
Hoppe
Lottieri
Huemer
Brennan
Politicians
Bastiat
Gladstone
Acton
Cleveland
Coolidge
Goldwater
Paul
Korwin-Mikke
Johnson
Milei
Hannan
Polis
National variants
South Africa
Spain
United Kingdom
United States
Historical background
Age of Enlightenment
Anarchism
Aristotelianism
Liberalism
classical
radical
Related topics
Abolitionism
Anti-collectivism
Anti-communism
Anti-fascism
Anti-socialism
Austro-libertarianism
Center for Libertarian Studies
Civil libertarianism
Classical liberalism
Conscientious objector
Constitutionalism
Cultural liberalism
Economic liberalism
Freeman on the land movement
Fusionism
Geolibertarianism
Georgism
Green libertarianism
Libertarian conservatism
Libertarian Democrats
Libertarian socialism
Libertarian Republicans
Libertarian science fiction
Libertarianism in South Africa
Libertarianism in the United Kingdom
Libertarianism in the United States
Objectivism
Public choice theory
Small government
Sovereign citizen movement
Technolibertarianism
Libertarianism portal
Anarchism portal
Politics portalvte
Locke's political theory was founded upon that of social contract. Unlike Thomas Hobbes, Locke believed that human nature is characterised by reason and tolerance. Like Hobbes, Locke believed that human nature allows people to be selfish. This is apparent with the introduction of currency. In a natural state, all people were equal and independent, and everyone had a natural right to defend his "life, health, liberty, or possessions".[63]: 198 Most scholars trace the phrase "Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness" in the American Declaration of Independence to Locke's theory of rights,[64] although other origins have been suggested.[65] Like Hobbes, Locke assumed that the sole right to defend in the state of nature was not enough, so people established a civil society to resolve conflicts in a civil way with help from government in a state of society. However, Locke never refers to Hobbes by name and may instead have been responding to other writers of the day.[66] Locke also advocated governmental separation of powers and believed that revolution is not only a right but an obligation in some circumstances. These ideas would come to have profound influence on the Declaration of Independence and the Constitution of the United States.
Accumulation of wealth[edit]
See also: Lockean proviso
According to Locke, unused property is wasteful and an offence against nature,[67] but, with the introduction of "durable" goods, men could exchange their excessive perishable goods for those which would last longer and thus not offend the natural law. In his view, the introduction of money marked the culmination of this process, making possible the unlimited accumulation of property without causing waste through spoilage.[68] He includes gold or silver as money because they may be "hoarded up without injury to anyone",[69] as they do not spoil or decay in the hands of the possessor. In his view, the introduction of money eliminates limits to accumulation. Locke stresses that inequality has come about by tacit agreement on the use of money, not by the social contract establishing civil society or the law of land regulating property. Locke was aware of a problem posed by unlimited accumulation, but did not consider it his task. He just implies that government would function to moderate the conflict between the unlimited accumulation of property and a more nearly equal distribution of wealth; he does not identify which principles that government should apply to solve this problem. However, not all elements of his thought form a consistent whole. For example, the labour theory of value in the Two Treatises of Government stands side by side with the demand-and-supply theory of value developed in a letter he wrote titled Some Considerations on the Consequences of the Lowering of Interest and the Raising of the Value of Money. Moreover, Locke anchors property in labour but, in the end, upholds unlimited accumulation of wealth.[70]
Ideas[edit]
Economics[edit]
On price theory[edit]
Locke's general theory of value and price is a supply-and-demand theory, set out in a letter to a member of parliament in 1691, titled Some Considerations on the Consequences of the Lowering of Interest and the Raising of the Value of Money.[71] In it, he refers to supply as quantity and demand as rent: "The price of any commodity rises or falls by the proportion of the number of buyers and sellers ... that which regulates the price ... [of goods] is nothing else but their quantity in proportion to their rent." The quantity theory of money forms a special case of this general theory. His idea is based on "money answers all things" (Ecclesiastes) or "rent of money is always sufficient, or more than enough" and "varies very little". Locke concludes that, as far as money is concerned, the demand for it is exclusively regulated by its quantity, regardless of whether the demand is unlimited or constant. He also investigates the determinants of demand and supply. For supply, he explains the value of goods as based on their scarcity and ability to be exchanged and consumed. He explains demand for goods as based on their ability to yield a flow of income. Locke develops an early theory of capitalisation, such as of land, which has value because "by its constant production of saleable commodities it brings in a certain yearly income". He considers the demand for money as almost the same as demand for goods or land: it depends on whether money is wanted as medium of exchange. As a medium of exchange, he states that "money is capable by exchange to procure us the necessaries or conveniences of life", and for loanable funds "it comes to be of the same nature with land by yielding a certain yearly income ... or interest".
Monetary thoughts[edit]
Locke distinguishes two functions of money: as a counter to measure value, and as a pledge to lay claim to goods. He believes that silver and gold, as opposed to paper money, are the appropriate currency for international transactions. Silver and gold, he says, are treated to have equal value by all of humanity and can thus be treated as a pledge by anyone, while the value of paper money is only valid under the government which issues it.
Locke argues that a country should seek a favourable balance of trade, lest it fall behind other countries and suffer a loss in its trade. Since the world money stock grows constantly, a country must constantly seek to enlarge its own stock. Locke develops his theory of foreign exchanges, by which in addition to commodity movements, there are also movements in country stock of money, and movements of capital determine exchange rates. He considers the latter less significant and less volatile than commodity movements. As for a country's money stock, if it is large relative to that of other countries, he says it will cause the country's exchange to rise above par, as an export balance would do.
Locke prepares estimates of the cash requirements for different economic groups (landholders, labourers, and brokers). In each group he posits that the cash requirements are closely related to the length of the pay period. He argues the brokers—the middlemen—whose activities enlarge the monetary circuit and whose profits eat into the earnings of labourers and landholders, have a negative influence on both personal and the public economy to which they supposedly contribute.[72]
Theory of value and property[edit]
Locke uses the concept of property in both broad and narrow terms: broadly, it covers a wide range of human interests and aspirations; more particularly, it refers to material goods. He argues that property is a natural right that is derived from labour. In Chapter V of his Second Treatise, Locke argues that the individual ownership of goods and property is justified by the labour exerted to produce such goods—"at least where there is enough [land], and as good, left in common for others" (para. 27)—or to use property to produce goods beneficial to human society.[73]
Locke states in his Second Treatise that nature on its own provides little of value to society, implying that the labour expended in the creation of goods gives them their value. From this premise, understood as a labour theory of value,[73] Locke developed a labour theory of property, whereby ownership of property is created by the application of labour. In addition, he believed that property precedes government and government cannot "dispose of the estates of the subjects arbitrarily". Karl Marx later critiqued Locke's theory of property in his own social theory.[74]
The human mind[edit]
The self[edit]
Locke defines the self as "that conscious thinking thing, (whatever substance, made up of whether spiritual, or material, simple, or compounded, it matters not) which is sensible, or conscious of pleasure and pain, capable of happiness or misery, and so is concerned for itself, as far as that consciousness extends".[75] He does not wholly ignore "substance", writing that "the body too goes to the making the man".[76] In his Essay, Locke explains the gradual unfolding of this conscious mind. Arguing against both the Augustinian view of man as originally sinful and the Cartesian position, which holds that man innately knows basic logical propositions, Locke posits an 'empty mind', a tabula rasa, which is shaped by experience; sensations and reflections being the two sources of all of our ideas.[77] He states in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding:
This source of ideas every man has wholly within himself; and though it be not sense, as having nothing to do with external objects, yet it is very like it, and might properly enough be called 'internal sense.'[78]
Locke's Some Thoughts Concerning Education is an outline on how to educate this mind. Drawing on thoughts expressed in letters written to Mary Clarke and her husband about their son,[79] he expresses the belief that education makes the man—or, more fundamentally, that the mind is an "empty cabinet":[80]
I think I may say that of all the men we meet with, nine parts of ten are what they are, good or evil, useful or not, by their education.
Locke also wrote that "the little and almost insensible impressions on our tender infancies have very important and lasting consequences".[80] He argues that the "associations of ideas" that one makes when young are more important than those made later because they are the foundation of the self; they are, put differently, what first mark the tabula rasa. In his Essay, in which both these concepts are introduced, Locke warns, for example, against letting "a foolish maid" convince a child that "goblins and sprites" are associated with the night, for "darkness shall ever afterwards bring with it those frightful ideas, and they shall be so joined, that he can no more bear the one than the other".[81]
This theory came to be called associationism, going on to strongly influence 18th-century thought, particularly educational theory, as nearly every educational writer warned parents not to allow their children to develop negative associations. It also led to the development of psychology and other new disciplines with David Hartley's attempt to discover a biological mechanism for associationism in his Observations on Man (1749).
Dream argument[edit]
Locke was critical of Descartes's version of the dream argument, with Locke making the counter-argument that people cannot have physical pain in dreams as they do in waking life.[82]
Religion[edit]
Religious beliefs[edit]
Some scholars have seen Locke's political convictions as being based from his religious beliefs.[83][84][85] Locke's religious trajectory began in Calvinist trinitarianism, but by the time of the Reflections (1695) Locke was advocating not just Socinian views on tolerance but also Socinian Christology.[86] However Wainwright (1987) notes that in the posthumously published Paraphrase (1707) Locke's interpretation of one verse, Ephesians 1:10, is markedly different from that of Socinians like Biddle, and may indicate that near the end of his life Locke returned nearer to an Arian position, thereby accepting Christ's pre-existence.[87][86]
Locke was at times not sure about the subject of original sin, so he was accused of Socinianism, Arianism, or Deism.[88] Locke argued that the idea that "all Adam's Posterity [are] doomed to Eternal Infinite Punishment, for the Transgression of Adam" was "little consistent with the Justice or Goodness of the Great and Infinite God", leading Eric Nelson to associate him with Pelagian ideas.[89] However, he did not deny the reality of evil. Man was capable of waging unjust wars and committing crimes. Criminals had to be punished, even with the death penalty.[90]
With regard to the Bible, Locke was very conservative. He retained the doctrine of the verbal inspiration of the Scriptures.[47] The miracles were proof of the divine nature of the biblical message. Locke was convinced that the entire content of the Bible was in agreement with human reason (The Reasonableness of Christianity, 1695).[91][47] Although Locke was an advocate of tolerance, he urged the authorities not to tolerate atheism, because he thought the denial of God's existence would undermine the social order and lead to chaos.[92] That excluded all atheistic varieties of philosophy and all attempts to deduce ethics and natural law from purely secular premises.[93] In Locke's opinion the cosmological argument was valid and proved God's existence. His political thought was based on Protestant Christian views.[93][94] Additionally, Locke advocated a sense of piety out of gratitude to God for giving reason to men.[95]
Philosophy from religion[edit]
Locke's concept of man started with the belief in creation.[96] Like philosophers Hugo Grotius and Samuel Pufendorf, Locke equated natural law with the biblical revelation.[97][98][99] Locke derived the fundamental concepts of his political theory from biblical texts, in particular from Genesis 1 and 2 (creation), the Decalogue, the Golden Rule, the teachings of Jesus, and the letters of Paul the Apostle.[100] The Decalogue puts a person's life, reputation and property under God's protection. Locke's philosophy on freedom is also derived from the Bible. Locke derived from the Bible basic human equality (including equality of the sexes), the starting point of the theological doctrine of Imago Dei.[101] To Locke, one of the consequences of the principle of equality was that all humans were created equally free and therefore governments needed the consent of the governed.[102] Locke compared the English monarchy's rule over the British people to Adam's rule over Eve in Genesis, which was appointed by God.[103] Following Locke's philosophy, the American Declaration of Independence founded human rights partially on the biblical belief in creation. Locke's doctrine that governments need the consent of the governed is also central to the Declaration of Independence.[104]
Library[edit]
Manuscripts, books and treatises[edit]
Locke's signature in Bodleian Locke 13.12. Photo taken at the Bodleian Library, Oxford.
Locke was an assiduous book collector and notetaker throughout his life. By his death in 1704, Locke had amassed a library of more than 3,000 books, a significant number in the seventeenth century.[105] Unlike some of his contemporaries, Locke took care to catalogue and preserve his library, and his will made specific provisions for how his library was to be distributed after his death. Locke's will offered Lady Masham the choice of "any four folios, eight quartos and twenty books of less volume, which she shall choose out of the books in my Library."[106] Locke also gave six titles to his "good friend" Anthony Collins, but Locke bequeathed the majority of his collection to his cousin Peter King (later Lord King) and to Lady Masham's son, Francis Cudworth Masham.[106]
Francis Masham was promised one "moiety" (half) of Locke's library when he reached "the age of one and twenty years."[106] The other "moiety" of Locke's books, along with his manuscripts, passed to his cousin King.[106] Over the next two centuries, the Masham portion of Locke's library was dispersed.[107] The manuscripts and books left to King, however, remained with King's descendants (later the Earls of Lovelace), until most of the collection was bought by the Bodleian Library, Oxford in 1947.[108] Another portion of the books Locke left to King was discovered by the collector and philanthropist Paul Mellon in 1951.[108] Mellon supplemented this discovery with books from Locke's library which he bought privately, and in 1978, he transferred his collection to the Bodleian.[108] One of Locke's famous books on politics, Two Treatises of Government, written and published in his lifetime
The holdings in the Locke Room at the Bodleian have been a valuable resource for scholars interested in Locke, his philosophy, practices for information management, and the history of the book. Many of the books still contain Locke's signature, which he often made on the pastedowns of his books. Many also include Locke's marginalia. The printed books in Locke's library reflected his various intellectual interests as well as his movements at different stages of his life. Locke travelled extensively in France and the Netherlands during the 1670s and 1680s, and during this time he acquired many books from the continent. Only half of the books in Locke's library were printed in England, while close to 40% came from France and the Netherlands.[109] These books cover a wide range of subjects. According to John Harrison and Peter Laslett, the largest genres in Locke's library were theology (23.8% of books), medicine (11.1%), politics and law (10.7%), and classical literature (10.1%).[110] The Bodleian library currently holds more than 800 of the books from Locke's library.[108] These include Locke's copies of works by several of the most influential figures of the seventeenth century, including
The Quaker William Penn: An address to Protestants of all perswasions (Bodleian Locke 7.69a)
The explorer Francis Drake: The world encompassed by Sir Francis Drake (Bodleian Locke 8.37c)
The scientist Robert Boyle: A discourse of things above reason (Bodleian Locke 7.272)
The bishop and historian Thomas Sprat: The history of the Royal-Society of London (Bodleian Locke 9.10a)
In addition to books owned by Locke, the Bodleian possesses more than 100 manuscripts related to Locke or written in his hand. Like the books in Locke's library, these manuscripts display a range of interests and provide different windows into Locke's activity and relationships. Several of the manuscripts include letters to and from acquaintances like Peter King (MS Locke b. 6) and Nicolas Toinard (MS Locke c. 45).[111] MS Locke f. 1–10 contain Locke's journals for most years between 1675 and 1704.[111] Some of the most significant manuscripts include early drafts of Locke's writings, such as his Essay Concerning Human Understanding (MS Locke f. 26).[111] The Bodleian also holds a copy of Robert Boyle's General History of the Air with corrections and notes Locke made while preparing Boyle's work for posthumous publication (MS Locke c. 37 ).[112] Other manuscripts contain unpublished works. Among others, MS. Locke e. 18 includes some of Locke's thoughts on the Glorious Revolution, which Locke sent to his friend Edward Clarke but never published.[113]
One of the largest categories of manuscript at the Bodleian comprises Locke's notebooks and commonplace books. The scholar Richard Yeo calls Locke a "Master Note-taker" and explains that "Locke's methodical note-taking pervaded most areas of his life."[114] In an unpublished essay "Of Study," Locke argued that a notebook should work like a "chest-of-drawers" for organising information, which would be a "great help to the memory and means to avoid confusion in our thoughts."[115] Locke kept several notebooks and commonplace books, which he organised according to topic. MS Locke c. 43 includes Locke's notes on theology, while MS Locke f. 18–24 contain medical notes.[111] Other notebooks, such as MS c. 43, incorporate several topics in the same notebook, but separated into sections.[111]
Page 1 of Locke's unfinished index in Bodleian Locke 13.12. Photo taken at the Bodleian Library, Oxford.
These commonplace books were highly personal and were designed to be used by Locke himself rather than accessible to a wide audience.[116] Locke's notes are often abbreviated and are full of codes which he used to reference material across notebooks.[117] Another way Locke personalised his notebooks was by devising his own method of creating indexes using a grid system and Latin keywords.[118] Instead of recording entire words, his indexes shortened words to their first letter and vowel. Thus, the word "Epistle" would be classified as "Ei".[119] Locke published his method in French in 1686, and it was republished posthumously in English in 1706. Some of the books in Locke's library at the Bodleian are a combination of manuscript and print. Locke had some of his books interleaved, meaning that they were bound with blank sheets in-between the printed pages to enable annotations. Locke interleaved and annotated his five volumes of the New Testament in French, Greek, and Latin (Bodleian Locke 9.103–107). Locke did the same with his copy of Thomas Hyde's Bodleian Library catalogue (Bodleian Locke 16.17), which Locke used to create a catalogue of his own library.[120]
Writing[edit]
List of major works[edit]
1689. A Letter Concerning Toleration.
1690. A Second Letter Concerning Toleration
1692. A Third Letter for Toleration
1689/90. Two Treatises of Government (published throughout the 18th century by London bookseller Andrew Millar by commission for Thomas Hollis)[121]
1689/90. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
1691. Some Considerations on the consequences of the Lowering of Interest and the Raising of the Value of Money
1693. Some Thoughts Concerning Education
1695. The Reasonableness of Christianity, as Delivered in the Scriptures
1695. A Vindication of the Reasonableness of Christianity
Major posthumous manuscripts[edit]
1660. First Tract of Government (or the English Tract)
c.1662. Second Tract of Government (or the Latin Tract)
1664. Questions Concerning the Law of Nature.[122]
1667. Essay Concerning Toleration
1706. Of the Conduct of the Understanding
1707. A paraphrase and notes on the Epistles of St. Paul to the Galatians, 1 and 2 Corinthians, Romans, Ephesians
See also[edit]
Liberalism portal
Libertarianism portal
List of liberal theorists
References[edit]
Notes[edit]
^ Kenyon (1977) adds: "Any unbiassed study of the position shows in fact that it was Filmer, not Hobbes, Locke or Sidney, who was the most influential thinker of the age" (p. 63).
Citations[edit]
^ Fumerton, Richard (2000). "Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 24 April 2018. Retrieved 19 August 2018.
^ Bostock, David (2009). Philosophy of Mathematics: An Introduction. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 43. All of Descartes, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume supposed that mathematics is a theory of our ideas, but none of them offered any argument for this conceptualist claim, and apparently took it to be uncontroversial.
^ Yolton, John W. (2000). Realism and Appearances: An Essay in Ontology. Cambridge University Press. p. 136.
^ "The Correspondence Theory of Truth". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2020. Archived from the original on 25 February 2014. Retrieved 19 August 2018.
^ Grigoris Antoniou; John Slaney, eds. (1998). Advanced Topics in Artificial Intelligence. Springer. p. 9.
^ Vere Claiborne Chappell, ed. (1994). The Cambridge Companion to Locke. Cambridge University Press. p. 56.
^ Meany, Paul "Cicero Was Locke’s Greatest Inspiration" Libertarianism.org
^ Jones 2010, p. 323.
^ a b Uzgalis, William (1 May 2018) [2 September 2001]. "John Locke". In E. N. Zalta (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 24 April 2021. Retrieved 2 June 2020.
^ Hansen, Hans V.; Pinto, Robert C., eds. (1995). Fallacies: classical and contemporary readings. University Park, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press. ISBN 978-0-271-01416-6. OCLC 30624864.
^ Locke, John (1690). "Book IV, Chapter XVII: Of Reason". An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Archived from the original on 3 March 2016. Retrieved 12 March 2015.
^ Locke, John (1690). Two Treatises of Government (10th ed.): Chapter II, Section 6. Project Gutenberg. Archived from the original on 16 November 2019. Retrieved 5 May 2018.
^ Grave tablet from 1705:
... That he was born on the 29th of August in the year of our Lord 1632, and that he died on the 28th of October in the year of our Lord 1704, this tablet, which itself will quickly perish, is a record.
See also: R. Woolhouse, Locke. A Biography, NY 2007, p. 1.
^ Hirschmann, Nancy J. (2009). Gender, Class, and Freedom in Modern Political Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. p. 79.
^ Sharma, Urmila; S. K. Sharma (2006). Western Political Thought. Washington: Atlantic Publishers. p. 440.
^ Korab-Karpowicz, W. Julian (2010). A History of Political Philosophy: From Thucydides to Locke. New York: Global Scholarly Publications. p. 291.
^ Becker, Carl Lotus (1922). The Declaration of Independence: a Study in the History of Political Ideas. New York: Harcourt, Brace. p. 27.
^ "Foreword and study guide to" John Locke's Two Treatises on Government: A Translation into Modern English, ISR Publications, 2013, p. ii. ISBN 978-0906321690
^ Baird, Forrest E.; Walter Kaufmann (2008). From Plato to Derrida. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall. pp. 527–529. ISBN 978-0-13-158591-1.
^ Locke, John (30 May 2024). "The Project Gutenberg eBook of Second Treatise Of Government, by John Locke". Archived from the original on 30 May 2024. Retrieved 3 June 2024.
^ "Encroachment, Adverse Possession, and Labor Theory | Antonin Scalia Law School". www.law.gmu.edu. Retrieved 3 June 2024.
^ Broad, C. D. (2000). Ethics And the History of Philosophy. UK: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-22530-4.
^ Roger Woolhouse (2007). Locke: A Biography. Cambridge University Press. p. 116.
^ "How Muslims indirectly helped in the American Revolution". EgyptToday. 14 June 2017. Retrieved 19 June 2024.
^ Kalın, İbrahim (10 March 2018). "'Hayy ibn Yaqdhan' and the European Enlightenment". Daily Sabah.
^ Russell, G. A. (1 January 1994). "The Impact Of The Philosophus Autodidactus: Pocockes, John Locke, And The Society Of Friends". The 'Arabick' Interest of the Natural Philosophers in Seventeenth-Century England. Brill. pp. 224–265. doi:10.1163/9789004247062_013. ISBN 978-90-04-24706-2. Retrieved 19 June 2024.
^ Attar, Samar (2007). The vital roots of European enlightenment: Ibn Tufayl's influence on modern Western thought. Lanham (Md.): Lexington books. ISBN 978-0-7391-1989-1.
^ Uzgalis, William (2022), "John Locke", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 7 March 2024
^ Henning, Basil Duke (1983), The House of Commons, 1660–1690, vol. 1, Boydell & Brewer, ISBN 978-0-436-19274-6, retrieved 28 August 2012
^ Laslett 1988, III. Two Treatises of Government and the Revolution of 1688.
^ a b Jan Bor, Errit Petersma & Jelle Kingma (eds.), De verbeelding van het denken. Geïllustreerde geschiedenis van de westerse en oosterse filosofie, Amsterdam/Antwerpen : Atlas Contact, 1996, ISBN 90-254-396, p. 260
^ Rebecca Newberger Goldstein (2006). Betraying Spinoza: The Renegade Jew Who Gave Us Modernity. New York: Schocken Books. pp. 260–261.
^ "John Locke - Enlightenment, Philosophy, Government | Britannica". www.britannica.com. 25 August 2024. Retrieved 4 September 2024.
^ Rogers, Graham A. J. "John Locke". Britannica Online. Archived from the original on 19 July 2017. Retrieved 3 September 2019.
^ Express, Britain. "Christ Church Cathedral, Oxford, History & Photos | Historic Oxford Guide". Britain Express.
^ Hoppit, Julian (2000). A Land of Liberty? England. 1689–1727. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 195.
^ a b Kenyon, John (1977). Revolution Principles: The Politics of Party. 1689–1720. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
^ Milton, John R. (2008) [2004]. "Locke, John (1632–1704)". Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (online ed.). Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/ref:odnb/16885. (Subscription or UK public library membership required.)
^ "The Three Greatest Men". American Treasures of the Library of Congress. Library of Congress. August 2007. Archived from the original on 20 June 2018. Retrieved 27 June 2018. Jefferson identified Bacon, Locke, and Newton as 'the three greatest men that have ever lived, without any exception'. Their works in the physical and moral sciences were instrumental in Jefferson's education and world view.
^ Jefferson, Thomas. "The Letters: 1743–1826 Bacon, Locke, and Newton". Archived from the original on 31 December 2009. Retrieved 13 June 2009. Bacon, Locke and Newton, whose pictures I will trouble you to have copied for me: and as I consider them as the three greatest men that have ever lived, without any exception, and as having laid the foundation of those superstructures which have been raised in the Physical & Moral sciences.
^ "Jefferson called Bacon, Newton, and Locke, who had so indelibly shaped his ideas, 'my trinity of the three greatest men the world had ever produced'". Explorer. Monticello. Archived from the original on 12 November 2012. Retrieved 28 August 2012.
^ Seigel, Jerrold (2005). The Idea of the Self: Thought and Experience in Western Europe since the Seventeenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
^ Taylor, Charles (1989). Sources of the Self: The Making of Modern Identity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
^ Schultz, Duane P. (2008). A History of Modern Psychology (9th ed.). Belmont, CA: Thomas Higher Education. pp. 47–48. ISBN 978-0-495-09799-0.
^ Wright, Edmund, ed. (2006). The Desk Encyclopedia of World History. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 374. ISBN 978-0-7394-7809-7.
^ McGrath, Alister (1998). Historical Theology, An Introduction to the History of Christian Thought. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. pp. 214–215.
^ a b c Heussi 1956.
^ Olmstead 1960, p. 18.
^ Stahl, H. (1957). "Baptisten". Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart (in German). 3 (1). col. 863.
^ Halbrooks, G. Thomas; Erich Geldbach; Bill J. Leonard; Brian Stanley (2011). "Baptists". Religion Past and Present. doi:10.1163/1877-5888_rpp_COM_01472. ISBN 978-90-04-14666-2. Archived from the original on 9 February 2021. Retrieved 2 June 2020..
^ Olmstead 1960, pp. 102–105.
^ Olmstead 1960, p. 5.
^ Cohen, Martin (2008), Philosophical Tales, Blackwell, p. 101.
^ Tully, James (2007), An Approach to Political Philosophy: Locke in Contexts, New York: Cambridge University Press, p. 128, ISBN 978-0-521-43638-0
^ Farr, J. (1986). "I. 'So Vile and Miserable an Estate': The Problem of Slavery in Locke's Political Thought". Political Theory. 14 (2): 263–289. doi:10.1177/0090591786014002005. JSTOR 191463. S2CID 145020766..
^ Farr, J. (2008). "Locke, Natural Law, and New World Slavery". Political Theory. 36 (4): 495–522. doi:10.1177/0090591708317899. S2CID 159542780..
^ Brewer 2017, p. 1052.
^ Brewer 2017, pp. 1053–1054.
^ Brewer 2017, pp. 1066 & 1072.
^ Diamond, J., The World Before Yesterday
^ Thompson, E. P. (1968). The Making of the English Working Class. Penguin.[page needed]
^ a b c Locke, John (1997a). "An Essay on the Poor Law". In Mark Goldie (ed.). Locke: Political Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
^ Locke, John. [1690] 2017. Second Treatise of Government Archived 16 November 2019 at the Wayback Machine (10th ed.), digitized by D. Gowan. Project Gutenberg. Retrieved 2 June 2020.
^ Zuckert, Michael (1996), The Natural Rights Republic, Notre Dame University Press, pp. 73–85
^ Wills, Garry (2002), Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence, Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co
^ Skinner, Quentin, Visions of Politics, Cambridge.
^ Locke, John (2009), Two Treatises on Government: A Translation into Modern English, Industrial Systems Research, p. 81, ISBN 978-0-906321-47-8[permanent dead link]
^ "John Locke: Inequality is inevitable and necessary". Department of Philosophy The University of Hong Kong. Archived from the original (MS PowerPoint) on 9 May 2009. Retrieved 1 September 2011.
^ Locke, John. "Second Treatise". The Founders Constitution. §§ 25–51, 123–126. Archived from the original on 11 September 2011. Retrieved 1 September 2011.
^ Cliff, Cobb; Foldvary, Fred. "John Locke on Property". The School of Cooperative Individualism. Archived from the original on 15 March 2012. Retrieved 14 October 2012.
^ Locke, John (1691), Some Considerations on the consequences of the Lowering of Interest and the Raising of the Value of Money, Marxists, archived from the original on 24 March 2015, retrieved 4 July 2007.
^ "Some Considerations of the Consequences of the Lowering of Interest, and Raising the Value of Money (Diplomatic)". www.newtonproject.ox.ac.uk. Archived from the original on 2 March 2024. Retrieved 2 March 2024.
^ a b Vaughn, Karen (1978). "John Locke and the Labor Theory of Value" (PDF). Journal of Libertarian Studies. 2 (4): 311–326. Archived from the original (PDF) on 19 October 2011.
^ Engle, Eric (15 September 2008). "Karl Marx's Intellectual Roots in John Locke". Postmodern Openings. 7 (7). Rochester, NY: 35–36. SSRN 1268545 – via SSRN.
^ Locke 1997b, p. 307.
^ Locke 1997b, p. 306.
^ The American International Encyclopedia, vol. 9, New York: JJ Little Co, 1954.
^ Angus, Joseph (1880). The Handbook of Specimens of English Literature. London: William Clowes and Sons. p. 324.
^ "Clarke [née Jepp], Mary". Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (online ed.). Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/ref:odnb/66720. (Subscription or UK public library membership required.)
^ a b Locke 1996, p. 10.
^ Locke 1997b, p. 357.
^ "Dreaming, Philosophy of – Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". utm.edu. Archived from the original on 31 January 2022. Retrieved 23 December 2016.
^ Forster, Greg (2005), John Locke's politics of moral consensus.
^ Parker, Kim Ian (2004), The Biblical Politics of John Locke, Canadian Corporation for Studies in Religion.
^ Locke, John (2002), Nuovo, Victor (ed.), Writings on religion, Oxford{{citation}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link).
^ a b Marshall, John (1994), John Locke: resistance, religion and responsibility, Cambridge, p. 426{{citation}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link).
^ Wainwright, Arthur W., ed. (1987). The Clarendon Edition of the Works of John Locke: A Paraphrase and Notes on the Epistle of St. Paul to the Galatians, 1 and 2 Corinthians, Romans, Ephesians. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 806. ISBN 978-0-19-824806-4.
^ Waldron 2002, pp. 27, 223.
^ Nelson 2019, pp. 7–8.
^ Waldron 2002, p. 145.
^ Henrich, D (1960), "Locke, John", Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart (in German), 3. Auflage, Band IV, Spalte 426
^ Waldron 2002, pp. 217 ff.
^ a b Waldron 2002, p. 13.
^ Dunn, John (1969), The Political Thought of John Locke: A Historical Account of the Argument of the 'Two Treatises of Government', Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, p. 99, [The Two Treatises of Government are] saturated with Christian assumptions..
^ Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1994. "John Locke's Epistemological Piety: Reason Is The Candle Of The Lord Archived 22 May 2020 at the Wayback Machine." Faith and Philosophy 11(4):572–591.
^ Waldron 2002, p. 142.
^ Elze, M (1958), "Grotius, Hugo", Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart (in German) 2(3):1885–1886.
^ Hohlwein, H (1961), "Pufendorf, Samuel Freiherr von", Die Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart (in German), 5(3):721.
^ Waldron 2002, p. 12.
^ Waldron 2002, pp. 22–43, 45–46, 101, 153–158, 195, 197.
^ Waldron 2002, pp. 21–43.
^ Waldron 2002, p. 136.
^ Locke, John (1947). Two Treatises of Government. New York: Hafner Publishing Company. pp. 17–18, 35, 38.
^ Becker, Carl. The Declaration of Independence: A Study in the History of Political Ideas. 1970 [1922]. Google Book Search. Revised ed., New York: Vintage Books. ISBN 978-0-394-70060-1.
^ Harrison, John; Laslett, Peter (1971). The Library of John Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 1.
^ a b c d Quoted in Harrison, John; Laslett, Peter (1971). The Library of John Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 8.
^ Harrison, John; Laslett, Peter (1971). The Library of John Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 57–61.
^ a b c d Bodleian Library. "Rare Books Named Collections". Archived from the original on 22 April 2015. Retrieved 15 March 2021.
^ Harrison, John; Laslett, Peter (1971). The Library of John Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 20.
^ Harrison, John; Laslett, Peter (1971). The Library of John Locke. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 18.
^ a b c d e Clapinson, M, and TD Rogers. 1991. Summary Catalogue of Post-Medieval Western Manuscripts in the Bodleian Library, Oxford. Vol. 2. Oxford University Press.
^ The works of Robert Boyle, vol. 12. Edited by Michael Hunter and Edward B. Davis. London: Pickering & Chatto, 2000, pp. xviii–xxi.
^ James Farr and Clayton Robers. "John Locke on the Glorious Revolution: a Rediscovered Document" Historical Journal 28 (1985): 395–398.
^ Richard Yeo, Notebooks, English Virtuosi (University of Chicago Press, 2014), 183.
^ John Locke, The Educational Writings of John Locke, ed. James Axtell (Cambridge University Press, 1968), 421.
^ Richard Yeo, Notebooks, English Virtuosi (University of Chicago Press, 2014), 218.
^ G. G. Meynell, "John Locke's Method of Common-Placing, as seen in His Drafts and His Medical Notebooks, Bodleian MSS Locke d. 9, f. 21 and f. 23," The Seventeenth Century 8, no. 2 (1993): 248.
^ Michael Stolberg, "John Locke's 'New Method of Making Common-Place-Books': Tradition, Innovation and Epistemic Effects," Early Science and Medicine 19, no. 5 (2014): 448–470.
^ John Locke, A New Method of Making Common-Place-Books (London: Printed for J. Greenood, 1706), 4.
^ G. G. Meynell, "A Database for John Locke's Medical Notebooks and Medical Reading," Medical History 42 (1997): 478
^ "The manuscripts, Letter from Andrew Millar to Thomas Cadell, 16 July, 1765. University of Edinburgh". www.millar-project.ed.ac.uk. Archived from the original on 15 January 2016. Retrieved 2 June 2016.
^ Locke, John. [1664] 1990. Questions Concerning the Law of Nature (definitive Latin text), translated by R. Horwitz, et al. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Sources[edit]
Ashcraft, Richard, 1986. Revolutionary Politics & Locke's Two Treatises of Government. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Discusses the relationship between Locke's philosophy and his political activities.
Ayers, Michael, 1991. Locke. Epistemology & Ontology Routledge (the standard work on Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding.)
Bailyn, Bernard, 1992 (1967). The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution. Harvard Uni. Press. Discusses the influence of Locke and other thinkers upon the American Revolution and on subsequent American political thought.
Brewer, Holly (October 2017). "Slavery, Sovereignty, and "Inheritable Blood": Reconsidering John Locke and the Origins of American Slavery". American Historical Review. 122 (4): 1038–1078. doi:10.1093/ahr/122.4.1038.
Cohen, Gerald, 1995. 'Marx and Locke on Land and Labour', in his Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality, Oxford University Press.
Cox, Richard, Locke on War and Peace, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1960. A discussion of Locke's theory of international relations.
Chappell, Vere, ed., 1994. The Cambridge Companion to Locke. Cambridge U.P. excerpt and text search Archived 29 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine
Dunn, John, 1984. Locke. Oxford Uni. Press. A succinct introduction.
———, 1969. The Political Thought of John Locke: An Historical Account of the Argument of the "Two Treatises of Government". Cambridge Uni. Press. Introduced the interpretation which emphasises the theological element in Locke's political thought.
Heussi, Karl (1956), Kompendium der Kirchengeschichte (in German), Tübingen, DE{{citation}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
Hudson, Nicholas, "John Locke and the Tradition of Nominalism," in: Nominalism and Literary Discourse, ed. Hugo Keiper, Christoph Bode, and Richard Utz (Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1997), pp. 283–299.
Jones, Howard (2010), "Epicurus and Epicureanism", in Grafton, Anthony; Most, Glenn W.; Settis, Salvatore (eds.), The Classical Tradition, Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, England: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, pp. 320–324, ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0
Laslett, Peter (1988), Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press to Locke's Two Treatises of Government
Locke, John (1996), Grant, Ruth W; Tarcov, Nathan (eds.), Some Thoughts Concerning Education and of the Conduct of the Understanding, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co, p. 10
Locke, John (1997b), Woolhouse, Roger (ed.), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, New York: Penguin Books
Locke Studies, appearing annually from 2001, formerly The Locke Newsletter (1970–2000), publishes scholarly work on John Locke.
Macpherson, C.B. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962). Establishes the deep affinity from Hobbes to Harrington, the Levellers, and Locke through to nineteenth-century utilitarianism.
Nelson, Eric (2019). The Theology of Liberalism: Political Philosophy and the Justice of God. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-24094-0. Archived from the original on 2 August 2020. Retrieved 24 April 2020.
Olmstead, Clifton E (1960), History of Religion in the United States, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall
Tully, James, 1980. A Discourse on Property : John Locke and his Adversaries. Cambridge Uni. Press
Waldron, Jeremy (2002), God, Locke, and Equality: Christian Foundations in Locke's Political Thought, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-89057-1
Yolton, John W., ed., 1969. John Locke: Problems and Perspectives. Cambridge Uni. Press.
Yolton, John W., ed., 1993. A Locke Dictionary. Oxford: Blackwell.
Zuckert, Michael, Launching Liberalism: On Lockean Political Philosophy. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.
External links[edit]
John Locke at Wikipedia's sister projects
Definitions from WiktionaryMedia from CommonsNews from WikinewsQuotations from WikiquoteTexts from WikisourceTextbooks from WikibooksResources from Wikiversity
Works[edit]
Works by John Locke in eBook form at Standard Ebooks
The Clarendon Edition of the Works of John Locke
Of the Conduct of the Understanding
Works by John Locke at Project Gutenberg
Works by or about John Locke at the Internet Archive
Works by John Locke at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)
Work by John Locke at Online Books
The Works of John Locke
1823 Edition, 10 volumes on PDF files, and additional resources Archived 10 August 2007 at the Wayback Machine
John Locke Manuscripts Archived 13 October 2009 at the Portuguese Web Archive
Updated versions of Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Second Treatise of Government, Letter on Toleration and Conduct of the Understanding, edited (i.e. modernised and abridged) by Jonathan Bennett
Resources[edit]
"John Locke". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
"John Locke: Epistemology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
"John Locke: Political Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Rickless, Samuel. "Locke on Freedom". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
John Locke Bibliography Archived 13 October 2009 at the Portuguese Web Archive
Locke Studies An Annual Journal of Locke Research Archived 13 May 2015 at the Wayback Machine
Hewett, Caspar, John Locke's Theory of Knowledge, UK: The great debate.
The Digital Locke Project, NL, archived from the original on 1 January 2014, retrieved 27 February 2007.
Portraits of Locke, UK: NPG, archived from the original on 24 May 2008, retrieved 18 April 2007.
Huyler, Jerome, Was Locke a Liberal? (PDF), Independent, archived from the original (PDF) on 26 March 2009, retrieved 2 August 2008, a complex and positive answer.
Kraynak, Robert P. (March 1980). "John Locke: from absolutism to toleration". American Political Science Review. 74 (1): 53–69. doi:10.2307/1955646. JSTOR 1955646. S2CID 146901427.
Anstey, Peter, John Locke and Natural Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2011.
'Hayy ibn Yaqdhan' and the European Enlightenment
Articles and topics related to John Locke
vteAge of EnlightenmentTopics
Atheism
Capitalism
Civil liberties
Classicism
Counter-Enlightenment
Critical thinking
Deism
Democracy
Empiricism
Encyclopédistes
Enlightened absolutism
Haskalah
Humanism
Human rights
Individualism
Liberalism
Liberté, égalité, fraternité
Lumières
Methodological skepticism
Midlands
Modernity
Natural philosophy
Objectivity
Progressivism
Rationality
Rationalism
Reason
Reductionism
Sapere aude
Science
Scientific method
Spanish America
Universality
Utopianism
ThinkersEngland
Addison
Ashley-Cooper
Bacon
Bentham
Collins
Gibbon
Godwin
Harrington
Hooke
Johnson
Locke
Milton
Newton
Pope
Price
Priestley
Reynolds
Sidney
Tindal
Wollstonecraft
France
d'Alembert
d'Argenson
Bayle
Beaumarchais
Chamfort
Châtelet
Condillac
Condorcet
Descartes
Diderot
Fontenelle
Gouges
Helvétius
d'Holbach
Jaucourt
La Mettrie
Lavoisier
Leclerc
Mably
Maréchal
Meslier
Montesquieu
Morelly
Pascal
Quesnay
Raynal
Sade
Turgot
Voltaire
Geneva
Abauzit
Bonnet
Burlamaqui
Prévost
Rousseau
Saussure
Germany
Goethe
Herder
Humboldt
Kant
Leibniz
Lessing
Lichtenberg
Mendelssohn
Pufendorf
Schiller
Thomasius
Weishaupt
Wieland
Wolff
Greece
Farmakidis
Feraios
Kairis
Korais
Ireland
Berkeley
Boyle
Burke
Swift
Toland
Italy
Beccaria
Galiani
Galvani
Genovesi
Pagano
Verri
Vico
Netherlands
Bekker
de la Court
Grotius
Huygens
Koerbagh
Leeuwenhoek
Mandeville
Meyer
Nieuwentyt
Spinoza
Swammerdam
Poland
Kołłątaj
Konarski
Krasicki
Niemcewicz
Poniatowski
Śniadecki
Staszic
Wybicki
Portugal
Carvalho e Melo
Romania
Budai-Deleanu
Cantemir
Maior
Micu-Klein
Șincai
Russia
Catherine II
Fonvizin
Kantemir
Kheraskov
Lomonosov
Novikov
Radishchev
Vorontsova-Dashkova
Serbia
Obradović
Mrazović
Spain
Cadalso
Charles III
Feijóo y Montenegro
Moratín
Jovellanos
Villarroel
Scotland
Beattie
Black
Blair
Boswell
Burnett
Burns
Cullen
Ferguson
Hume
Hutcheson
Hutton
Mill
Newton
Playfair
Reid
Smith
Stewart
United States
Franklin
Jefferson
Madison
Mason
Paine
Romanticism →
Category
vteLiberalismIdeas
Consent of the governed
Due process
Democracy
Economic liberalism
Economic globalization
Equality
Gender
Legal
Federalism
Freedom
Economic
Market
Trade
Press
Religion
Speech
Harm principle
Internationalism
Invisible hand
Labor theory of property
Laissez-faire
Liberty
Negative
Positive
Limited government
Market economy
Natural monopoly
Open society
Permissive society
Popular sovereignty
Property
Private
Public
Rights
Civil and political
Natural and legal
To own property
To bear arms
Rule of law
Secularism
Secular humanism
Separation of church and state
Separation of powers
Social contract
Social justice
Social services
Welfare state
Whig historySchoolsClassical
Economic
Fiscal
Neo
Equity feminism
Georgist
Radical
Anti-clerical
Civic nationalism
Republican
Utilitarian
Whig
Physiocratic
Encyclopaedist
Conservative
Liberal conservatism
National
Ordo
Social
Green
Liberal feminism
Ecofeminism
Liberal socialism
Social democracy
Progressivism
Third Way
Other
Constitutional
Constitutional patriotism
Cultural
Corporate
International
Libertarianism
Left-libertarianism
Geolibertarianism
Neoclassical liberalism
Paleolibertarianism
Right-libertarianism
Radical centrism
Religious
Christian
Islamic
Secular
Techno
By regionAfrica
Egypt
Nigeria
Senegal
South Africa
Tunisia
Zimbabwe
Asia
China
Hong Kong
India
Iran
Israel
Japan
South Korea
Anti-Chinilpa
Centrist reformist
Progressive
Philippines
Turkey
Europe
Albania
Armenia
Austria
Belgium
Bulgaria
Croatia
Cyprus
Czech lands
Denmark
Estonia
Finland
France
Orléanist
Georgia
Germany
Greece
Hungary
Italy
Berlusconism
Liberism
Latvia
Lithuania
Luxembourg
Macedonia
Moldova
Montenegro
Netherlands
Norway
Portugal
Romania
Russia
Serbia
Slovakia
Slovenia
Spain
Sweden
Switzerland
Turkey
Ukraine
United Kingdom
Gladstonian
Libertarian
Manchester
Muscular
Radical
Whiggist
Latin America andthe Caribbean
Bolivia
Brazil
Lulism
Chile
Colombia
Cuba
Ecuador
Honduras
Mexico
Nicaragua
Panama
Paraguay
Peru
Uruguay
North America
Canada
United States
Jacksonian
Jeffersonian
Libertarian
Modern
Progressive
Oceania
Australia
Small-l
New Zealand
Philosophers
Milton
Locke
Spinoza
Montesquieu
Voltaire
Rousseau
Smith
Kant
Turgot
Burke
Priestley
Paine
Beccaria
Condorcet
Bentham
Korais
De Gouges
Wollstonecraft
Staël
Say
Humboldt
Constant
Ricardo
Guizot
List
Bastiat
Martineau
Emerson
Tocqueville
Mill
Spencer
Arnold
Acton
Weber
Hobhouse
Croce
Cassirer
Mises
Ortega
Keynes
Collingwood
Čapek
Hu
Hayek
Popper
Aron
Berlin
Friedman
Rawls
Sen
Nozick
Kymlicka
BadawiPoliticians
Jefferson
Kołłątaj
Madison
Artigas
Bolívar
Broglie
Lamartine
Macaulay
Kossuth
Deák
Cobden
Mazzini
Juárez
Lincoln
Gladstone
Cavour
Sarmiento
Mommsen
Naoroji
Itagaki
Levski
Kemal
Deakin
Milyukov
Lloyd George
Venizelos
Ståhlberg
Gokhale
Rathenau
Madero
Einaudi
King
Roosevelt
Pearson
Ohlin
Kennedy
Jenkins
Balcerowicz
Verhofstadt
Obama
MacronOrganisations
Africa Liberal Network
Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe
Alliance of Liberals and Democrats for Europe Party
Arab Liberal Federation
Council of Asian Liberals and Democrats
European Democratic Party
European Liberal Youth
International Alliance of Libertarian Parties
International Federation of Liberal Youth
Liberal International
Liberal Network for Latin America
Liberal parties
Liberal South East European Network
Related topics
Anti-authoritarianism
Anti-communism
Bias in American academia
Bias in the media
Capitalism
Democratic
Centrism
Radical centrism
Economic freedom
Egalitarianism
Empiricism
Humanism
Individualism
Anarchist
Land value tax
Libertarianism
Left
Right
Pirate Party
Progressivism
Sexually liberal feminism
Utilitarianism
Liberalism Portal
vteLibertarianismOrigins
Age of Enlightenment
Anarchism
Aristotelianism
Liberalism
classical
radical
SchoolsLibertarian capitalism(Right-libertarianism)
Anarcho-capitalism
Autarchism
Christian libertarianism
Conservative libertarianism
Consequentialist libertarianism
Fusionism
Libertarian transhumanism
Minarchism
Natural-rights libertarianism
Neo-classical liberalism
Bleeding-heart libertarianism
Paleolibertarianism
Propertarianism
Voluntaryism
Libertarian socialism(Left-libertarianism)
Anarchism
collectivist
communist
free-market
agorism
green
individualist
insurrectionary
libertarian communism
mutualism
philosophical
social
syndicalist
Autonomism
Communalism
Guild socialism
Libertarian Marxism
Syndicalism
Concepts
Abstention
Academic freedom
Age of consent reform
Anti-authoritarianism
Anti-capitalism
Antimilitarism
Anti-statism
Artistic freedom
Civil liberties
Class struggle
Cognitive liberty
Counter-economics
Crypto-anarchism
Decentralization
Decriminalization of sex work
Departurism
Drug liberalization
Direct action
Economic freedom
Egalitarianism
Evictionism
Expropriative anarchism
Federalism (anarchist)
Free association (Marxism and anarchism)
Free love
Free market
Free-market environmentalism
Free migration
Free trade
Freedom of assembly
Freedom of association
Freedom of choice
Freedom of conscience
Freedom of contract
Freedom of information
Freedom of religion
Freedom of speech
Freedom of thought
Gift economy
Homestead principle
Illegalism
Individualism
Individualist feminism
Individual reclamation
Liberty
Libertarianism (metaphysics)
Localism
Natural law
Natural rights and legal rights
Night-watchman state
Non-aggression principle
Non-interventionism
Participatory economics
Propaganda of the deed
Property is theft!
Refusal of work
Reproductive rights
Right to die
Right to privacy
Right to sexuality
Self-governance
Self-ownership
Single tax
Social ecology
Spontaneous order
Squatting
Stateless society
Tax resistance
Voluntary association
Voluntary society
Workers' councils
Workers' self-management
PhilosophersLeft-wing
Bakunin
Bookchin
Camus
Chomsky
Cleyre
Déjacque
Fourier
Godwin
Goldman
Guérin
Hodgskin
Kropotkin
Marcuse
Öcalan
Proudhon
Warren
Tucker
Right-wing
Bastiat
Block
Brennan
Emerson
D. Friedman
M. Friedman
R. Friedman
Goldwater
Hayek
Herbert
Hoppe
Jillette
Kinsella
Korwin-Mikke
Lane
Locke
von Mises
de Molinari
Nock
Nozick
Paterson
Rand
Read
Rothbard
Simon
Spencer
Stossel
Other
George
Hess
Konkin III
de La Boétie
McElroy
Paine
Spooner
Stirner
Szasz
Thoreau
Politicians
Cleveland
Coolidge
Farage
Gandhi
Johnson
Jorgensen
Korwin-Mikke
Milei
Paul
Sarwark
Issues
Abortion
Affirmative action
Anarcho-capitalism and minarchism
Capital punishment
Criticism
Foreign intervention
Immigration
Intellectual property
Internal debates
LGBT rights
Objectivism
Political alliances
Political parties
Theories of law
War on Drugs
Works
Atlas Shrugged (1957)
The Market for Liberty (1970)
For a New Liberty: The Libertarian Manifesto (1973)
Law, Legislation and Liberty (1973–1979)
Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974)
Free to Choose (1980)
Related
Abolitionism
Anti-collectivism
Anti-communism
Anti-fascism
Anti-socialism
Austro-libertarianism
Center for Libertarian Studies
Civil libertarianism
Classical liberalism
Conscientious objector
Constitutionalism
Cultural liberalism
Economic liberalism
Freeman on the land movement
Fusionism
Geolibertarianism
Georgism
Green libertarianism
Libertarian conservatism
Libertarian Democrats
Libertarian socialism
Libertarian Republicans
Libertarian science fiction
Libertarianism in South Africa
Libertarianism in the United Kingdom
Libertarianism in the United States
Objectivism
Public choice theory
Small government
Sovereign citizen movement
Technolibertarianism
Libertarianism portal
Outline of libertarianism
vteMetaphysicsTheories
Abstract object theory
Action theory
Anti-realism
Determinism
Dualism
Enactivism
Essentialism
Existentialism
Free will
Idealism
Libertarianism
Liberty
Materialism
Meaning of life
Monism
Naturalism
Nihilism
Phenomenalism
Realism
Physicalism
Relativism
Scientific realism
Solipsism
Spiritualism
Subjectivism
Substance theory
Theory of forms
Truthmaker theory
Type theory
Concepts
Abstract object
Anima mundi
Category of being
Causality
Causal closure
Cogito, ergo sum
Concept
Embodied cognition
Entity
Essence
Existence
Experience
Hypostatic abstraction
Idea
Identity
Information
Data
Insight
Intelligence
Intention
Linguistic modality
Matter
Meaning
Mental representation
Mind
Motion
Nature
Necessity
Object
Ontology
Pattern
Perception
Physical object
Principle
Property
Qualia
Quality
Reality
Relation
Self
Soul
Subject
Substantial form
Thought
Time
Truth
Type–token distinction
Universal
Unobservable
Value
more ...
Metaphysicians
Parmenides
Plato
Aristotle
Lucretius
Proclus
Plotinus
Avicenna
Scotus
Aquinas
Suárez
Descartes
Spinoza
Locke
Malebranche
Newton
Leibniz
Wolff
Reid
Berkeley
Hume
Kant
Hegel
Schopenhauer
Bolzano
Kierkegaard
Lotze
Peirce
Nietzsche
Meinong
Bergson
Whitehead
Russell
Moore
Collingwood
Wittgenstein
Heidegger
Carnap
Ryle
Sartre
Quine
Davidson
Strawson
Anscombe
Deleuze
Dummett
Armstrong
Putnam
Plantinga
Kripke
Lewis
Baudrillard
Parfit
more ...
Notable works
Sophist (c. 350 BC)
Timaeus (c. 350 BC)
Nyāya Sūtras (c. 200 BC)
De rerum natura (c. 80 BC)
Metaphysics (c. 50)
Enneads (c. 270)
Daneshnameh-ye Alai (c. 1000)
Meditations on First Philosophy (1641)
Ethics (1677)
A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710)
Monadology (1714)
Critique of Pure Reason (1781)
Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (1783)
The Phenomenology of Spirit (1807)
The World as Will and Representation (1818)
Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments (1846)
Being and Time (1927)
Being and Nothingness (1943)
Simulacra and Simulation (1981)
Related topics
Axiology
Cosmology
Epistemology
Feminist metaphysics
Interpretations of quantum mechanics
Mereology
Meta-
Phenomenology
Philosophy of mind
Philosophy of psychology
Philosophy of self
Philosophy of space and time
Teleology
Category
Philosophy portal
vteEpistemologyEpistemologists
Thomas Aquinas
Augustine of Hippo
William Alston
Robert Audi
A. J. Ayer
George Berkeley
Laurence BonJour
Gilles Deleuze
Keith DeRose
René Descartes
John Dewey
Fred Dretske
Edmund Gettier
Alvin Goldman
Nelson Goodman
Paul Grice
Anil Gupta
Susan Haack
David Hume
Immanuel Kant
Søren Kierkegaard
Peter Klein
Saul Kripke
Hilary Kornblith
David Lewis
John Locke
G. E. Moore
John McDowell
Robert Nozick
Alvin Plantinga
Plato
Duncan Pritchard
James Pryor
Hilary Putnam
W. V. O. Quine
Thomas Reid
Bertrand Russell
Gilbert Ryle
Wilfrid Sellars
Susanna Siegel
Ernest Sosa
P. F. Strawson
Baruch Spinoza
Timothy Williamson
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Nicholas Wolterstorff
Vienna Circle
more...
Theories
Coherentism
Constructivism
Contextualism
Empiricism
Evolutionary epistemology
Fallibilism
Feminist epistemology
Fideism
Foundationalism
Holism
Infinitism
Innatism
Naïve realism
Naturalized epistemology
Phenomenalism
Positivism
Rationalism
Reductionism
Reliabilism
Representational realism
Skepticism
Transcendental idealism
Concepts
A priori knowledge
A posteriori knowledge
Analysis
Analytic–synthetic distinction
Belief
Common sense
Descriptive knowledge
Exploratory thought
Epistemic injustice
Epistemic virtue
Gettier problem
Induction
Internalism and externalism
Justification
Knowledge
Objectivity
Privileged access
Problem of induction
Problem of other minds
Perception
Procedural knowledge
Proposition
Regress argument
Simplicity
Truth
more...
Related articles
Outline of epistemology
Faith and rationality
Formal epistemology
Metaepistemology
Philosophy of perception
Philosophy of science
Social epistemology
Virtue epistemology
Category
Task Force
Stubs
Discussion
vtePropertyBy owner
Collective
Common
Communal
Community
Crown
Customary
Cooperative
Private
Public
Self
Social
State
Unowned
By nature
Croft
Estate (landed)
Intangible
Intellectual
indigenous
Personal
Tangible
real
Commons
Common land
Common-pool resource
Digital
Global
Information
Knowledge
Theory
Bundle of rights
Commodity
fictitious commodities
Common good (economics)
Excludability
First possession
appropriation
homestead principle
Free-rider problem
Game theory
Georgism
Gift economy
Labor theory of property
Law of rent
rent-seeking
Legal plunder
Natural rights
Ownership
Property rights
primogeniture
usufruct
women's
Right to property
Rivalry
Tragedy of the commons
anticommons
Applications
Acequia (watercourse)
Ejido (agrarian land)
Estate
legal
literary
real
Forest types
Huerta
Inheritance
executor
Land tenure
Property law
alienation
easement
restraint on alienation
real estate
title
Rights
Air
Fishing
Forest-dwelling (India)
Freedom to roam
Grazing
pannage
Hunting
Land
aboriginal
indigenous
squatting
Littoral
Mineral
Bergregal
Right of way (transit)
Right of way (property access)
Water
prior-appropriation
riparian
Disposession/redistribution
Bioprospecting
biopiracy
Collectivization
Eminent domain
Enclosure
Eviction
Expropriation
Farhud
Forced migration
population transfer
repatriation
Illegal fishing
Illegal logging
Land Back
Land reform
Legal plunder
Piracy
Poaching
Primitive accumulation
Privatization
Regulatory taking
Slavery
bride buying
human trafficking
spousal
husband-selling
wife selling
wage
Tax
inheritance
poll
progressive
property
Theft
Scholars(key work)
Frédéric Bastiat
The Law
Ronald Coase
Friedrich Engels
The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State
Henry George
Progress and Poverty
Garrett Hardin
David Harvey
John Locke
Two Treatises of Government
Karl Marx
Das Kapital
Marcel Mauss
The Gift
John Stuart Mill
Elinor Ostrom
Karl Polanyi
The Great Transformation
Pierre-Joseph Proudhon
What Is Property?
David Ricardo
Murray N. Rothbard
The Ethics of Liberty
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
The Social Contract
Adam Smith
The Wealth of Nations
Categories: Property
Property law
by country
vtePolitical philosophyTerms
Authority
Citizenship
Duty
Elite
Emancipation
Freedom
Government
Hegemony
Hierarchy
Justice
Law
Legitimacy
Liberty
Monopoly
Nation
Obedience
Peace
People
Pluralism
Power
Progress
Propaganda
Property
Regime
Revolution
Rights
Ruling class
Society
Sovereignty
State
Utopia
War
Government
Aristocracy
Autocracy
Bureaucracy
Dictatorship
Democracy
Gerontocracy
Meritocracy
Monarchy
Oligarchy
Plutocracy
Technocracy
Theocracy
Ideologies
Agrarianism
Anarchism
Capitalism
Christian democracy
Colonialism
Communism
Communitarianism
Confucianism
Conservatism
Corporatism
Distributism
Environmentalism
Fascism
Feminism
Feudalism
Imperialism
Islamism
Liberalism
Libertarianism
Localism
Marxism
Monarchism
Multiculturalism
Nationalism
Nazism
Populism
Republicanism
Social Darwinism
Social democracy
Socialism
Third Way
Concepts
Balance of power
Bellum omnium contra omnes
Body politic
Clash of civilizations
Common good
Consent of the governed
Divine right of kings
Family as a model for the state
Monopoly on violence
Natural law
Negative and positive rights
Night-watchman state
Noble lie
Noblesse oblige
Open society
Ordered liberty
Original position
Overton window
Separation of powers
Social contract
State of nature
Statolatry
Tyranny of the majority
PhilosophersAntiquity
Aristotle
Chanakya
Cicero
Confucius
Han Fei
Lactantius
Mencius
Mozi
Plato
political philosophy
Polybius
Shang
Sun Tzu
Thucydides
Xenophon
Middle Ages
Alpharabius
Aquinas
Averroes
Bruni
Dante
Gelasius
al-Ghazali
Ibn Khaldun
Marsilius
Muhammad
Nizam al-Mulk
Ockham
Plethon
Wang
Early modernperiod
Boétie
Bodin
Bossuet
Calvin
Campanella
Filmer
Grotius
Guicciardini
Hobbes
political philosophy
James
Leibniz
Locke
Luther
Machiavelli
Milton
More
Müntzer
Pufendorf
Spinoza
Suárez
18th and 19thcenturies
Bakunin
Bastiat
Beccaria
Bentham
Bolingbroke
Bonald
Burke
Carlyle
Comte
Condorcet
Constant
Cortés
Engels
Fichte
Fourier
Franklin
Godwin
Haller
Hegel
Herder
Hume
Iqbal
political philosophy
Jefferson
Kant
political philosophy
Le Bon
Le Play
Madison
Maistre
Marx
Mazzini
Mill
Montesquieu
Nietzsche
Owen
Paine
Renan
Rousseau
Sade
Saint-Simon
Smith
Spencer
de Staël
Stirner
Taine
Thoreau
Tocqueville
Tucker
Voltaire
20th and 21stcenturies
Agamben
Ambedkar
Arendt
Aron
Badiou
Bauman
Benoist
Berlin
Bernstein
Burnham
Chomsky
Dmowski
Du Bois
Dugin
Dworkin
Evola
Foucault
Fromm
Fukuyama
Gandhi
Gentile
Gramsci
Guénon
Habermas
Hayek
Hoppe
Huntington
Kautsky
Kirk
Kropotkin
Laclau
Lenin
Luxemburg
Mansfield
Mao
Marcuse
Maurras
Michels
Mises
Mosca
Mouffe
Negri
Nozick
Nussbaum
Oakeshott
Ortega
Pareto
Popper
Qutb
Rand
Rawls
Röpke
Rothbard
Russell
Sartre
Schmitt
Scruton
Shariati
Sorel
Spann
Spengler
Strauss
Sun
Taylor
Voegelin
Walzer
Weber
Works
Republic (c. 375 BC)
Politics (c. 350 BC)
De re publica (51 BC)
Treatise on Law (c. 1274)
Monarchia (1313)
The Prince (1532)
Leviathan (1651)
Two Treatises of Government (1689)
The Spirit of Law (1748)
The Social Contract (1762)
Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790)
Rights of Man (1791)
Elements of the Philosophy of Right (1820)
Democracy in America (1835–1840)
The Communist Manifesto (1848)
On Liberty (1859)
The Revolt of the Masses (1929)
The Road to Serfdom (1944)
The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945)
The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951)
A Theory of Justice (1971)
The End of History and the Last Man (1992)
Related
Authoritarianism
Collectivism and individualism
Conflict theories
Contractualism
Critique of political economy
Egalitarianism
Elite theory
Elitism
History of political thought
Institutional discrimination
Jurisprudence
Justification for the state
Machiavellianism
Political ethics
Political spectrum
Left-wing politics
Centrism
Right-wing politics
Political theology
Political violence
Separation of church and state
Separatism
Social justice
Statism
Totalitarianism
Index
Category:Political philosophy
vtePhilosophy of educationPhilosophers
Dewey
Fröbel
Herbart
Humboldt
Locke
Montessori
Pestalozzi
Piaget
Rousseau
Steiner
Vygotsky
more...
Concepts
Active learning
Student-centred learning
What to teach
Classicism
Contemplative education
Critical pedagogy
Critical theory
Critical thinking
Democratic education
Educational essentialism
Educational existentialism
Educational perennialism
Idealism
Popular education
Pragmatism
Progressive education
Realism
Social reconstructionism
Theism
How and whom to teach
Behaviorism (philosophy of education)
Cognitivism (philosophy of education)
Compulsory education
Constructivism (philosophy of education)
Criticism of schooling
Humanism (philosophy of education)
Montessori education
Unschooling
Waldorf education
Related
Cognitive science
Psychology
Category
Discussion
vteAmerican Revolutionary WarOrigins of the American RevolutionPhilosophy
American Enlightenment
John Locke
Colonial history
Liberalism
Republicanism
Freedom of religion
Rights of Englishmen
No taxation without representation
Common Sense
Spirit of '76
"All men are created equal"
"Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness"
"Consent of the governed"
Expansionism
Settler colonialism
Royalists
Pitt–Newcastle ministry
Bute ministry
Grenville ministry
First Rockingham ministry
Chatham ministry
Grafton ministry
North ministry
Second Rockingham ministry
Shelburne ministry
Fox–North coalition
Loyalists
Black Loyalist
Related BritishActs of Parliament
Navigation
Iron
Molasses
Royal Proclamation of 1763
Sugar
Currency
Quartering
Stamp up i.p.o
Declaratory
Townshend
Tea
Quebec
Intolerable
Conciliatory Resolution
Restraining
Proclamation of Rebellion
Prohibitory
Colonials
Loyal Nine
Stamp Act Congress
Declaration of Rights and Grievances
Virginia Association
Daughters of Liberty
Sons of Liberty
Patriots
Black Patriots
Committees of correspondence
Committees of safety
Letters from a Farmer in Pennsylvania
Massachusetts Circular Letter
Suffolk Resolves
First Continental Congress
Continental Association
Minutemen
Provincial Congress
Second Continental Congress
United Colonies
Olive Branch Petition
Declaration of the Causes and Necessity of Taking Up Arms
Committee of Secret Correspondence
Halifax Resolves
Lee Resolution
Declaration of Independence
Model Treaty
Articles of Confederation and Perpetual Union
Confederation Congress
Events
French and Indian War
Treaty of Paris (1763)
Boston Massacre
British credit crisis of 1772–1773
Gaspee affair
Hutchinson letters affair
Boston Tea Party
Philadelphia Tea Party
Powder Alarm
Combatants
Campaigns
Theaters
Battles
Events
Colonies
CombatantsUnited Colonies/Thirteen Colonies
Continental Congress
Army
Navy
Marines
Kingdom of Great Britain
Parliament
British Army
Royal Navy
European allies of King George III
Colonial allies
France
Franco-American Treaty
Army
Navy
Hortalez et Cie
German supporters of Congress
Campaigns andtheaters
Boston
Quebec
Nova Scotia
New York and New Jersey
Saratoga
Philadelphia
Northern
Northern after Saratoga
Southern
Western
Yorktown
Naval battles
Major battles
Lexington and Concord
Boston
Capture of Fort Ticonderoga
Bunker Hill
Quebec
Valcour Island
Long Island
Harlem Heights
Fort Washington
Trenton
Assunpink Creek
Princeton
Siege of Fort Ticonderoga
Bennington
Saratoga
Brandywine
Germantown
Monmouth
St. Lucia
Grenada
Stony Point
Sullivan Expedition
Savannah
Gibraltar
Cape St. Vincent
Charleston
Connecticut Farms
Springfield
Camden
Kings Mountain
Cowpens
Pensacola
Guilford Court House
Lochry's Defeat
Chesapeake
Yorktown
The Saintes
Other events
Staten Island Peace Conference
"First Salute"
Washington's crossing of the Delaware River
Conway Cabal
Valley Forge
Entry of France into war
Carlisle Peace Commission
Gordon Riots
Pennsylvania Mutiny of 1781
Sint Eustatius
Newburgh Conspiracy
Pennsylvania Mutiny of 1783
Related conflicts
Cherokee–American wars
Fourth Anglo-Dutch War
Second Anglo-Mysore War
Involvement (by colony or location)Rebel colonies
Connecticut
Delaware
Georgia
Maryland
Massachusetts
New Hampshire
New Jersey
New York
North Carolina
Pennsylvania
Rhode Island
South Carolina
Virginia
Loyal colonies
East Florida
Nova Scotia
Quebec
West Florida
LeadersBritishMilitary
Arbuthnot
Brant
Burgoyne
Campbell
Carleton
Clinton
Cornwallis
Fraser
Gage
Graves
Richard Howe
William Howe
Knyphausen
Rodney
Civilian
King George III
Amherst
Barrington
Germain
North
Rockingham
Sandwich
Shelburne
ColonialMilitary
Washington
Alexander
Allen
Arnold
Barry
Claghorn
Clark
Duportail
Gates
Greene
Hamilton
Hopkins
Jones
de Kalb
Knox
Lafayette
Charles Lee
Lincoln
Mercer
Montgomery
Nicholson
Putnam
Rodney
St. Clair
Schuyler
von Steuben
Sullivan
Ward
Wayne
Civilian
John Adams
Samuel Adams
Carroll
Dickinson
Franklin
Hancock
Hanson
Henry
Huntington
Jay
Jefferson
Laurens
Richard Henry Lee
McKean
Morris
Revere
Rush
Witherspoon
Colonial alliesFrench
Louis XVI
Beaumarchais
d'Estaing
de Grasse
de Guichen
Luzerne
de Rochambeau
Suffren
Vergennes
Aftermath
Society of the Cincinnati
Treaty of Paris (1783)
Evacuation Day (1783)
Ratification Day (1784)
Constitutional Convention
The Federalist Papers
Constitution
Bill of Rights
Shays's Rebellion
Jay Treaty
Related topics
Military
Prisoners
The Turtle
Political
Founding Fathers
Diplomacy
Liberty Tree
Yankee Doodle
Other topics
Timeline of the American Revolution
African Americans in the Revolutionary War
Dogs in the American Revolutionary War
Intelligence in the American Revolutionary War
Women in the American Revolution
Financial costs of the war
Continental currency banknotes
Continental Currency dollar coin
Libertas Americana
Commemoration
films
television
theater
Independence Day
Patriots' Day
Pulaski Memorial Day
Washington's Birthday
Jefferson's Birthday
Von Steuben Day
Minor holidays
Centennial
Sesquicentennial
Bicentennial
Semiquincentennial
Children of the American Revolution
Daughters of the American Revolution
Sons of the American Revolution
Sons of the Revolution
Charters of Freedom Rotunda
Museum of the American Revolution
Authority control databases InternationalISNIVIAFFASTWorldCatNationalGermanyUnited StatesFranceBnF dataJapanItalyAustraliaCzech RepublicSpainPortugalNetherlandsNorwayLatviaCroatiaChileGreeceArgentinaKoreaSwedenPolandVaticanIsraelFinlandCataloniaAcademicsCiNiizbMATHArtistsULANFIDPeopleTroveDeutsche BiographieDDBOtherIdRefSNAC